REVIEW ARTICLE
What is Semantics?
Richmond H. Thomason
Version 1 prepared: December 1, 1996
Version 2 (minor revisions): March 27, 2012
Copyright, Richmond H. Thomason, 1996
Comments Invited: Send Comments to rthomaso@umich.edu
Richmond H. Thomason
Version 1 prepared: December 1, 1996
Version 2 (minor revisions): March 27, 2012
Copyright, Richmond H. Thomason, 1996
Comments Invited: Send Comments to rthomaso@umich.edu
Semantics is the study
of the meaning of linguistic expressions. The language can be a natural
language, such as English or Navajo, or an artificial language, like a computer
programming language. Meaning in natural languages is mainly studied by
linguists. In fact, semantics is one of the main branches of contemporary
linguistics. Theoretical computer scientists and logicians think about
artificial languages. In some areas of computer science, these divisions are
crossed. In machine translation, for instance, computer scientists may want to
relate natural language texts to abstract representations of their meanings; to
do this, they have to design artificial languages for representing meanings.
There are strong
connections to philosophy. Earlier in this century, much work in semantics was
done by philosophers, and some important work is still done by philosophers.
Anyone who speaks a
language has a truly amazing capacity to reason about the meanings of texts.
Take, for instance, the sentence
(S) I can't untie that knot with one hand.
Even though you have
probably never seen this sentence, you can easily see things like the
following:
1. The sentence is about the abilities of whoever spoke or wrote it. (Call this person the speaker.)
2. It's also about a knot, maybe one that the speaker is pointing at.
3. The sentence denies that the speaker has a certain ability. (This is the contribution of the word ‘can't’.)
4. Untying is a way of making something not tied.
5. The sentence doesn't mean that the knot has one hand; it has to do with how many hands are used to do the untying.
The meaning of a
sentence is not just an unordered heap of the meanings of its words. If that
were true, then ‘Cowboys ride horses’ and ‘Horses ride cowboys’ would mean the
same thing. So we need to think about arrangements of meanings.
Here is an arrangement
that seems to bring out the relationships of the meanings in sentence (S).
Not [ I [ Able [ [
[Make [Not [Tied]]] [That knot ] ] [With One Hand] ] ] ]
The unit [Make [Not
[Tied]] here corresponds to the act of untying; it contains a subunit
corresponding to the state of being untied. Larger units correspond to the act
of untying-that-knot and to the act to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand. Then this
act combines with Able to make a larger unit, corresponding to the state of
being-able-to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand. This unit combines with I to make
the thought that I have this state -- that is, the thought that
I-am-able-to-untie-that-knot-with-one-hand. Finally, this combines with Not and
we get the denial of that thought.
This idea that
meaningful units combine systematically to form larger meaningful units, and
understanding sentences is a way of working out these combinations, has
probably been the most important theme in contemporary semantics.
Linguists who study
semantics look for general rules that bring out the relationship between form,
which is the observed arrangement of words in sentences, and meaning. This is
interesting and challenging, because these relationships are so complex.
A semantic rule for
English might say that a simple sentence involving the word ‘can't’ always
corresponds to a meaning arrangement like
Not [ Able ... ],
but never to one like
Able [ Not ... ].
For instance, ‘I can't
dance’ means that I'm unable to dance; it doesn't mean that I'm able not to
dance.
To assign meanings to
the sentences of a language, you need to know what they are. It is the job of
another area of linguistics, called syntax, to answer this question, by
providing rules that show how sentences and other expressions are built up out
of smaller parts, and eventually out of words. The meaning of a sentence
depends not only on the words it contains, but on its syntactic makeup: the
sentence
(S) That can hurt you,
for instance, is
ambiguous -- it has two distinct meanings. These correspond to two distinct
syntactic structures. In one structure ‘That’ is the subject and ‘can’ is an
auxiliary verb (meaning “able”), and in the other ‘That can’ is the subject and
‘can’ is a noun (indicating a sort of container).
Because the meaning of
a sentence depends so closely on its syntactic structure, linguists have given
a lot of thought to the relations between syntactic structure and meaning; in
fact, evidence about ambiguity is one way of testing ideas about syntactic
structure.
You would expect an
expert in semantics to know a lot about what meanings are. But linguists
haven't directly answered this question very successfully. This may seem like
bad news for semantics, but it is actually not that uncommon for the basic
concepts of a successful science to remain problematic: a physicist will
probably have trouble telling you what time is. The nature of meaning, and the
nature of time, are foundational questions that are debated by philosophers.
We can simplify the
problem a little by saying that, whatever meanings are, we are interested in
literal meaning. Often, much more than the meaning of a sentence is conveyed
when someone uses it. Suppose that Carol says ‘I have to study’ in answer to
‘Can you go to the movies tonight?’. She means that she has to study that
night, and that this is a reason why she can't go to the movies. But the
sentence she used literally means only that she has to study. Nonliteral
meanings are studied in pragmatics, an area of linguistics that deals with
discourse and contextual effects.
But what is a literal
meaning? There are four sorts of answers: (1) you can dodge the question, or
(2) appeal to usage, or (3) appeal to psychology, or (4) treat meanings as real
objects.
(1) The first idea
would involve trying to reconstruct semantics so that it can be done without
actually referring to meanings. It turns out to be hard to do this -- at least,
if you want a theory that does what linguistic semanticists would like a theory
to do. But the idea was popular earlier in the twentieth century, especially in
the 1940s and 1950s, and has been revived several times since then, because
many philosophers would prefer to do without meanings if at all possible. But
these attempts tend to ignore the linguistic requirements, and for various
technical reasons have not been very successful.
(2) When an English
speaker says ‘It's raining’ and a French speaker says ‘Il pleut’ you can say
that there is a common pattern of usage here. But no one really knows how to
characterize what the two utterances have in common without somehow invoking a
common meaning. (In this case, the meaning that it's raining.) So this idea
doesn't seem to really explain what meanings are.
(3) Here, you would try
to explain meanings as ideas. This is an old idea, and is still popular;
nowadays, it takes the form of developing an artificial language that is
supposed to capture the "inner cognitive representations" of an ideal
thinking and speaking agent. The problem with this approach is that the methods
of contemporary psychology don't provide much help in telling us in general
what these inner representations are like. This idea doesn't seem yet to lead
to a methodology that can produce a workable semantic theory.
(4) If you say that the
meaning of ‘Mars’ is a certain planet, at least you have a meaning relation
that you can come to grips with. There is the word ‘Mars’ on the one hand, and
on the other hand there is this big ball of matter circling around the sun.
This clarity is good, but it is hard to see how you could cover all of language
this way. It doesn't help us very much in saying what sentences mean, for
instance. And what about the other meaning of ‘Mars’? Do we have to believe in
the Roman god to say that ‘Mars’ is meaningful? And what about ‘the largest
number’?
The approach that most
semanticists endorse is a combination of (1) and (4). Using techniques similar
to those used by mathematicians, you can build up a complex universe of
abstract objects that can serve as meanings (or denotations) of various sorts
of linguistic expressions. Since sentences can be either true or false, the
meanings of sentences usually involve the two truth values true and false. You
can make up artificial languages for talking about these objects; some
semanticists claim that these languages can be used to capture inner cognitive
representations. If so, this would also incorporate elements of (3), the
psychological approach to meanings. Finally, by restricting your attention to
selected parts of natural language, you can often avoid hard questions about
what meanings in general are. This is why this approach to some extent dodges
the general question of what meanings are. The hope would be, however, that as
more linguistic constructions are covered, better and more adequate
representations of meaning would emerge.
Though "truth
values" may seem artificial as components of meaning, they are very handy
in talking about the meaning of things like negation; the semantic rule for
negative sentences says that their meanings are like that of the corresponding
positive sentences, except that the truth value is switched, false for true and
true for false. ‘It isn't raining’ is true if ‘It is raining’ is false, and
false if ‘It is raining’ is true.
Truth values also
provide a connection to validity and to valid reasoning. (It is valid to infer
a sentence S2 from S1 in case S1 couldn't possibly be true when S2 is false.)
This interest in valid reasoning provides a strong connection to work in the
semantics of artificial languages, since these languages are usually designed
with some reasoning task in mind. Logical languages are designed to model
theoretical reasoning such as mathematical proofs, while computer languages are
intended to model a variety of general and special purpose reasoning tasks.
Validity is useful in working with proofs because it gives us a criterion for
correctness. It is useful in much the same way with computer programs, where it
can sometimes be used to either prove a program correct, or (if the proof
fails) to discover flaws in programs.
These ideas (which
really come from logic) have proved to be very powerful in providing a theory
of how the meanings of natural-language sentences depend on the meanings of the
words they contain and their syntactic structure. Over the last forty years or
so, there has been a lot of progress in working this out, not only for English,
but for a wide variety of languages. This is made much easier by the fact that
human languages are very similar in the kinds of rules that are needed for
projecting meanings from words to sentences; they mainly differ in their words,
and in the details of their syntactic rules.
Recently, there has
been more interest in lexical semantics -- that is, in the semantics of words.
Lexical semantics is not so much a matter of trying to write an "ideal
dictionary". (Dictionaries contain a lot of useful information, but don't
really provide a theory of meaning or good representations of meanings.)
Rather, lexical semantics is concerned with systematic relations in the
meanings of words, and in recurring patterns among different meanings of the
same word. It is no accident, for instance, that you can say ‘Sam ate a grape’
and ‘Sam ate’, the former saying what Sam ate and the latter merely saying that
Sam ate something. This same pattern occurs with many verbs.
Logic is a help in
lexical semantics, but lexical semantics is full of cases in which meanings
depend subtly on context, and there are exceptions to many generalizations. (To
undermine something is to mine under it; but to understand something is not to
stand under it.) So logic doesn't carry us as far here as it seems to carry us
in the semantics of sentences.
Natural-language
semantics is important in trying to make computers better able to deal directly
with human languages. In one typical application, there is a program people
need to use. Running the program requires using an artificial language
(usually, a special-purpose command language or query-language) that tells the
computer how to do some useful reasoning or question-answering task. But it is
frustrating and time-consuming to teach this language to everyone who may want
to interact with the program. So it is often worthwhile to write a second
program, a natural language interface, that mediates between simple commands in
a human language and the artificial language that the computer understands.
Here, there is certainly no confusion about what a meaning is; the meanings you
want to attach to natural language commands are the corresponding expressions
of the programming language that the machine understands. Many computer
scientists believe that natural language semantics is useful in designing
programs of this sort. But it is only part of the picture. It turns out that
most English sentences are ambiguous to a depressing extent. (If a sentence has
just five words, and each of these words has four meanings, this alone gives
potentially 1,024 possible combined meanings.) Generally, only a few of these
potential meanings will be at all plausible. People are very good at focusing
on these plausible meanings, without being swamped by the unintended meanings.
But this takes common sense, and at present we do not have a very good idea of
how to get computers to imitate this sort of common sense. Researchers in the
area of computer science known as Artificial Intelligence are working on that.
Meanwhile, in building natural-language interfaces, you can exploit the fact
that a specific application (like retrieving answers from a database)
constrains the things that a user is likely to say. Using this, and other
clever techniques, it is possible to build special purpose natural-language
interfaces that perform remarkably well, even though we are still a long way
from figuring out how to get computers to do general-purpose natural-language
understanding.
Semantics probably
won't help you find out the meaning of a word you don't understand, though it
does have a lot to say about the patterns of meaningfulness that you find in
words. It certainly can't help you understand the meaning of one of
Shakespeare's sonnets, since poetic meaning is so different from literal
meaning. But as we learn more about semantics, we are finding out a lot about
how the world's languages match forms to meanings. And in doing that, we are
learning a lot about ourselves and how we think, as well as acquiring knowledge
that is useful in many different fields and applications.
The strengthness of
this journal is it give us big information about semantics. It’s really clear and make the reader easy to
understand. Why? Because it dissect the example word by word. This journal
trying to make the reader really understand because the word choice that it
used is quite simple. When you read the journal you will feel like there is
someone who explain about this in front of you.
The weakness of this journal
is it just give one example to dissect so maybe the reader feel unsatisfied.
Conclusion
The journal
has been explain about what semantic is, strong connection to philosophy,
semantic rule of English, what literal meaning is and etc. I think in this
journal we just can find minim weakness so it’s good for learner English like us.
Komentar
Posting Komentar